According to Marmor, “[l]egal instructions are meant to
generate concrete results, providing people with particular reasons for action,
thus aiming to affect our conduct in some specified ways.” That laws are
“meant” to generate concrete results is not a claim about the “nature” of law,
but an empirical claim about the attitudes of certain people about law, or perhaps
(to tighten the comparison with art, discussed in the previous post) an
empirical claim about the intentions of those who make them. Either way, Marmor
does not provide any empirical evidence to support it.
If not meant as an empirical claim, then it must be
understood as an interpretation of the practice, something like “based on what
laws are created for, they are best understood as meant to generate
concrete results.” These are normative claims, and, as it happens, they are not
universally accepted. Legal scholars argued that there is sometimes value in laws
not always generating concrete results, that there is value in laws that are purposely
vague as they generate political
debate, deter
conduct, be flexible enough for dealing with changing circumstances, and so
on.
Marmor might reply that these scholars are wrong, that they don’t understand the nature of law. Now, if they asked him on what basis he makes such claims, what would he point to? He could point to the way people talk about law, think about law, what they use law for, and so on. But these are all empirical claims. Is there anything else? If he insists that this is just intuitive or obvious that this is what law is, others can reply that their intuitions are different. If he says “just look at how we use law” (again, an empirical claim, or an interpretive one), they will reply with other examples in which laws are used differently.
When the empirical nature of these claims is made explicit, another
question arises: why assume that as a conceptual matter (as opposed to a
conclusion of a normative argument) all “legal instructions are meant to
generate concrete results”? There is no difficulty in conceiving the
possibility that some laws meant (and therefore designed) to “generate
concrete results” while others that are meant (and therefore designed) for
their multiplicity of meaning.
This challenge is not purely theoretical. There are some
fairly known “legal instructions” included in familiar legal documents called
constitutions. To say that that they are all “meant” to generate concrete
results would be, to put it gently, controversial. Marmor may have noticed
this, which is why he talks about what law is “generally speaking,” but the law
is full of what Holmes called “moral phraseology” outside constitutional texts,
which is anything but concrete. The law also employs additional terminology (for
example, “foreseeability”) that does not have an immediate moral equivalent but
is anything but concrete.
In any case, once this is not a claim about necessities but
about empirical tendencies, we are in the world of empirical sociology. To be clear, all this does not exclude such
findings from the domain of jurisprudence, for there is no reason to think that
jurisprudence is limited only to what is necessarily true about law. It does
mean, however, that to show that these empirical tendencies are true requires
more than mere speculation.
No comments:
Post a Comment